mirror of
https://github.com/Smaug123/static-site-pdfs
synced 2025-10-13 03:08:40 +00:00
171 lines
11 KiB
TeX
171 lines
11 KiB
TeX
\documentclass[11pt]{amsart}
|
|
\usepackage{geometry}
|
|
\geometry{a4paper}
|
|
\usepackage{graphicx}
|
|
\usepackage{amssymb}
|
|
\usepackage{epstopdf}
|
|
\usepackage{mdframed}
|
|
\usepackage{hyperref}
|
|
\usepackage{lmodern}
|
|
|
|
% Reproducible builds
|
|
\pdfinfoomitdate=1
|
|
\pdftrailerid{}
|
|
\pdfsuppressptexinfo=-1
|
|
|
|
\DeclareGraphicsRule{.tif}{png}{.png}{`convert #1 `dirname #1`/`basename #1 .tif`.png}
|
|
|
|
\newmdtheoremenv{defn}{Definition}
|
|
\newmdtheoremenv{thm}{Theorem}
|
|
\newmdtheoremenv{motiv}{Motivation}
|
|
|
|
\title{Friedberg-Muchnik theorem}
|
|
\author{Patrick Stevens, with tip of the hat to Dr Thomas Forster}
|
|
\date{5th February 2016}
|
|
|
|
\begin{document}
|
|
|
|
\maketitle
|
|
|
|
\tiny \begin{center} \url{https://www.patrickstevens.co.uk/misc/FriedbergMuchnik/FriedbergMuchnik.pdf} \end{center}
|
|
|
|
\normalsize
|
|
|
|
\section{Introduction}
|
|
|
|
We consider Turing machines which query an oracle $O$: that is, they come equipped with an extra instruction ``call the oracle with this input'', where a call to the oracle is simply a test for membership in $O$.
|
|
|
|
We may supply different oracles to the same Turing machine, and potentially get different results: for example, the Turing machine which has as its only instruction ``output the result of calling the oracle on my input'' precisely mimics the oracle.
|
|
|
|
Recall that a set $A$ is \emph{semi-decidable} if there is a Turing machine $T$ such that for all $n \in \mathbb{N}$, $T(n)$ halts iff $n \in A$.
|
|
|
|
\
|
|
|
|
\begin{thm}[Friedberg-Muchnik theorem] There are semidecidable sets $A$ and $B$ such that for all Turing machines $T$ which may query an oracle, the following fail to be equivalent:
|
|
|
|
\begin{enumerate}
|
|
\item $T$-querying-$B$ doesn't halt with output $0$
|
|
\item $T$-querying-$B$ has input in $A$
|
|
\end{enumerate}
|
|
|
|
and the following fail to be equivalent:
|
|
\begin{enumerate}
|
|
\item $T$-querying-$A$ doesn't halt with output $0$
|
|
\item $T$-querying-$A$ has input in $B$
|
|
\end{enumerate}
|
|
\end{thm}
|
|
|
|
\
|
|
|
|
That is, we can find two semidecidable sets $A$ and $B$ such that neither allows a Turing machine to decide the other, where by ``$T$ decides $A$'' we mean ``$T$ halts and outputs $0$ iff its input is not in $A$, and it halts and outputs $1$ iff its input is in $A$''.
|
|
(Equivalently, $T$ is a machine which computes the characteristic function of $A$.)
|
|
|
|
\section{Proof}
|
|
|
|
We can enumerate all the Turing machines which call an oracle; write $[ n ]^X$ for the $n$th Turing machine in the enumeration, calling oracle $X$.
|
|
|
|
What would it mean for the Friedberg-Muchnik theorem to hold?
|
|
We would be able to find $e_n$ (resp. $f_n$) that witness in turn that the $n$th Turing machine doesn't manage to decide $A$ in the presence of $B$ (resp. $B$ in the presence of $A$).
|
|
|
|
That is, it would be enough to show that:
|
|
|
|
\
|
|
|
|
\begin{thm} There are semidecidable sets $A, B$ such that for all $n \in \mathbb{N}$:
|
|
\begin{itemize}
|
|
\item there is $e_n \in \mathbb{N}$ such that \begin{itemize} \item $e_n \in A$ but $[n]^B(e_n)$ halts with output $0$, or \item $e_n \not \in A$ but $[n]^B(e_n)$ fails to halt, or halts at something other than $0$ \end{itemize}
|
|
\item there is $f_n \in \mathbb{N}$ such that \begin{itemize} \item $f_n \in B$ but $[n]^A(f_n)$ halts with output $0$, or \item $f_n \not \in B$ but $[n]^A(f_n)$ fails to halt, or halts at something other than $0$ \end{itemize}
|
|
\end{itemize}
|
|
\end{thm}
|
|
|
|
\
|
|
|
|
The way we are going to do this is as follows.
|
|
We'll construct our $A$ and $B$ iteratively, starting from the empty set and only ever adding things in to our current attempts.
|
|
|
|
For each $n \in \mathbb{N}$, we can make an infinite list of ``possible'' witnesses: numbers which might eventually be our choice for $e_n$.
|
|
We don't care what these guesses are at the moment, but we just insist that they be disjoint and sorted into increasing order.
|
|
Write $$G_i = \{g^{(i)}_1, g^{(i)}_2, \dots \}$$ for the set of possibilities for $e_i$, and $$H_i = \{ h^{(i)}_1, h^{(i)}_2, \dots \}$$ for the set of possibilities for $f_i$.
|
|
(I emphasise again that we don't assume any properties of these numbers, other than that $g^{(i)}_m$ and $h^{(i)}_m$ are increasing with $m$, and that no $g^{(i)}_m, g^{(j)}_n, h^{(k)}_p, h^{(l)}_q$ are equal.)
|
|
|
|
Now, at time-step $0$, we have no information about what's going to be in $A$ and $B$, so let $$A_0 = B_0 = \emptyset$$
|
|
|
|
Every $G_i$ and $H_i$ is looking for a witness among its members.
|
|
We assign a priority order to them: $$G_1 > H_1 > G_2 > H_2 > \dots$$
|
|
The idea is that the high-priority sets quickly decide on their witness, and the lower-priority sets get to choose their witness subject to not being allowed to mess up any higher-priority set's decision.
|
|
|
|
At time-step $t$, we've already built $A_{t-1}, B_{t-1}$ as our best guesses at $A$ and $B$.
|
|
We seek an $e_i$ for any $G_i$ which hasn't got one (for $1 \leq i \leq t$), and then we can work on finding $f_i$ for the $H_i$ next.
|
|
|
|
Run the machines $[i]^{B_{t-1}}$ for $i=1, 2, \dots, t$, for $t$ steps each, each on input $g^{(i)}_1$.
|
|
This will approximate $[i]^B$, because $B_{t-1} \subseteq B = \cup_{t=1}^{\infty} B_t$, but it is by no means exactly what we need yet.
|
|
|
|
\begin{itemize}
|
|
\item If our machine $[i]^{B_{t-1}}$ ever attempts to query its oracle on a value greater than $\text{max}(B_{t-1})$, we declare that the machine crashes for this round, and sits out.
|
|
Indeed, $B_{t-1}$ is incomplete at this point as a reflection of $B$ - we only have information about it up to $\text{max}(B_{t-1})$ - so it would be useless to try and infer information about $B$ from parts of $B_{t-1}$ which are even bigger than that maximum.
|
|
|
|
\item If $[i]^{B_{t-1}}$ halts at something other than $0$, then it's no use to us: it can't possibly be a witness we can add to $B$, because such witnesses $e_i$ must satisfy ``$[i]^B(e_i)$ halts at $0$''.
|
|
So $G_i$ will sit out of this round.
|
|
|
|
\item If $[i]^{B_{t-1}}$ fails to halt in the allotted $t$ steps, it is likewise not something we can add to $B$, because we can't (yet) even prove that the machine \emph{halts} on this input, let alone that it halts on $0$.
|
|
So $G_i$ will again sit out of this round.
|
|
|
|
\item But if $[i]^{B_{t-1}}$ halts and outputs $0$ in the allotted $t$ steps, we're in business: for some collection of $i$, we have found some things ($g^{(i)}_1$) that might serve as witnesses.
|
|
Throw each of these into $B_{t-1}$ to make $B_t$.
|
|
\end{itemize}
|
|
|
|
OK. Now $G_i$ is happy, but remember we might have had a side-effect here, because if (for the sake of argument) $G_1$ had already decided on its witness during time-step $t-1$, it made that decision with reference to $B_{t-1}$ and not with reference to $B_t$.
|
|
The fact that $g^{(i)}_1$ is now in our $B$-guess may alter the computation that $[1]^{B_{t-1}}$ performed to decide on its witness.
|
|
(This is because $[1]^{B_{t-1}}(e_1)$ is not in general equal to $[1]^{B_t}(e_1)$.)
|
|
|
|
How can we ensure that in fact $G_1$'s witness isn't broken?
|
|
Well, $[1]$ is a finite machine which we have run for a finite time, so it can only have asked the oracle for values up to some finite number $\beta_1$ before it halted.
|
|
So if we can make sure we only ever added $g^{(i)}_n$ to $B_{t-1}$ if it was above $\beta_1$, then we haven't actually changed $B$ from the point of view of $[1]$.
|
|
Even after $B_{t-1}$ becomes $B_t$, the computation $[1]^{B_{t-1}}$ performs is exactly the same as the computation $[1]^{B_t}$ performs, because the oracles are the same on all points $[1]$ might query.
|
|
|
|
Therefore, after adding something from $G_i$ to make $B_t$, we need to delete all numbers below $\beta_i$ from all lower-priority $G_j$ and $H_j$.
|
|
(This is easy to do because of our stipulation that the $G_j$ be listed with elements in ascending order.)
|
|
That way, no $G_j$ will never even consider any element that breaks a higher-priority $G_i$.
|
|
|
|
Once we've found the $G$-witnesses at time-step $t$, we can find the $H$-witnesses in exactly the same way; and finally, we move on to time-step $t+1$.
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Problem} This procedure works pretty well, but there's a problem with it. You might like to meditate on this for a few minutes, because it's revealed in the next paragraph.
|
|
|
|
The problem is simply that while no lower-priority entry can break a higher-priority one, the reverse might happen!
|
|
It might be that $G_1, G_2, G_3$ take ten steps of execution before halting, while $G_4$ halts after just one step and so decides on its witness immediately (that is, at time $t=4$, as opposed to $G_1$'s $t=10$).
|
|
Subsequently, $G_1$ will decide on its witness, and the act of throwing its witness into $B$ might break $G_4$'s choice.
|
|
Remember that $G_4$ only eliminated breaking-values from \emph{lower}-priority $G_j$, not the higher-priority $G_1$.
|
|
(Allowing it to eliminate breaking-values from higher-priority sets could cause the entire protocol to enter an infinite loop, with $G_1$ and $G_4$ each invalidating the results of the other on successive time-steps.)
|
|
|
|
However, this isn't actually too much of a problem.
|
|
Since $G_1$ can only ever decide on its witness once (being the highest-priority), that means $H_1$ will only ever need to decide twice; $G_2$ only ever needs to decide at most four times (it could be first to pick its witness, then $H_1$ overrules it, then it picks again, then $G_1$ overrules it and $H_1$, then it picks again, then $H_1$ overrules it, and finally it picks again).
|
|
In general, the $i$th element of the priority order can only be overruled $2^i - 1$ times.
|
|
|
|
So if $G_i$ is overruled, we can just keep churning through the procedure, chucking more and more elements into $B$; $G_i$ can only be overruled finitely many times, and it has infinitely many elements in its list to play with, so eventually it will work its way into a position when it can never be overruled.
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Final problem}
|
|
OK, this works fine if every $G_i$ eventually finds a witness.
|
|
But there's another case: $G_1$ may never find a witness.
|
|
For example, $[1]^{B_t}(g^{(1)}_1)$ may never halt, or it may halt but output the value $1$ instead of $0$ (so the protocol sees it as ``uninteresting'' and just repeatedly tells $G_1$ to sit out of the round).
|
|
|
|
But remember that we're trying to construct a witness that a certain equivalence fails, and so far we've been constructing witnesses that it fails in one of its directions.
|
|
(Remember: the equivalence we want to fail is that $T^B$ halts with $0$ iff it has input not in $A$.)
|
|
We could still win by finding $e_1$ such that $[1]^B(e_1)$ fails to halt at $0$ despite not being in $A$.
|
|
And look! We've precisely got one of those elements, and it's $g^{(1)}_1$.
|
|
|
|
\section{Summary}
|
|
|
|
The output of this procedure is a pair of sets $$\displaystyle A = \cup_{t=1}^{\infty} A_t, B = \cup_{t=1}^{\infty} B_t$$
|
|
which are semi-decidable (because we built them as a union of finite sets $A_t, B_t$).
|
|
For each Turing machine $[i]^X$, we have a witness $e_n$, such that:
|
|
\begin{itemize}
|
|
\item either $[i]^B(e_n)$ halts with output $0$ and $e_n \in A$, or
|
|
\item $[i]^B(e_n)$ fails to halt, or halts with output not equal to $0$, and $e_n \not \in A$.
|
|
\end{itemize}
|
|
(This can be proved by induction: if $e_n$ is a witness at time $t$ and it is never overruled, then it remains a witness when we pass to $B$, because by construction its computation doesn't change on passing to $B$.)
|
|
|
|
That is, no Turing machine $[i]^B$ decides $A$.
|
|
|
|
Likewise, no Turing machine $[i]^A$ decides $B$.
|
|
|
|
\end{document} |