Files
static-site-pdfs/ParametricBoundedLoeb2016/ParametricBoundedLoeb2016.tex
2023-10-01 21:06:27 +01:00

154 lines
7.7 KiB
TeX

\documentclass[11pt]{amsart}
\usepackage{geometry}
\geometry{a4paper}
\usepackage{graphicx}
\usepackage{amssymb}
\usepackage{mdframed}
\usepackage{hyperref}
\usepackage{lmodern}
% Reproducible builds
\pdfinfoomitdate=1
\pdftrailerid{}
\pdfsuppressptexinfo=-1
\newmdtheoremenv{thm}{Theorem}[section]
\newcommand{\prov}{\square}
\newcommand{\encode}[1]{\ulcorner #1 \urcorner}
\newcommand{\lob}{L\"ob's Theorem}
\title{Parametric bounded version of L\"ob's theorem}
\author{Patrick Stevens}
\date{24th July 2016}
\begin{document}
\maketitle
\tiny \begin{center} \url{https://www.patrickstevens.co.uk/misc/ParametricBoundedLoeb2016/ParametricBoundedLoeb2016.pdf} \end{center}
\normalsize
\section{Introduction}
I was recently made aware of a preprint\cite{critch} of a paper which proves a bounded version of \lob.
\
\begin{thm}[Parametric Bounded L\"ob]
If $\prov A$ is the operator ``there exists a proof of $A$ in Peano arithmetic''
and $\prov_k A$ is the operator ``there exists a proof of $A$ in $k$ or fewer lines in Peano arithmetic'',
then for every formula $p$ of one free variable in the language of PA, and every computable $f: \mathbb{N} \to \mathbb{N}$
which grows sufficiently fast, it is true that
$$(\exists \hat{k})[\color{red}(\vdash [\forall k][\color{green}\prov_{f(k)} p(k) \to p(k) \color{red}])\color{black} \Rightarrow \color{blue}(\vdash [\forall k > \hat{k}][p(k)]) \color{black}]$$
\end{thm}
\
(Colour is used only to emphasise logical chunks of the formula.)
The paper gives plenty of motivation about why this result should be interesting and useful:
section 6 of the paper, for instance, is an application to the one-shot Prisoner's Dilemma
played between agents who have access to each other's source code.
However, I believe that while the theorem may be true and the proof may be correct,
its application may not be as straightforward as the paper suggests.
\section{Background}
\begin{thm}[\lob]
Suppose $\prov \encode{A}$ denotes ``the formula $A$ with G\"odel number $\encode{A}$ is provable''.
If $$\mathrm{PA} \vdash (\prov \encode{P} \to P)$$
then
$$\mathrm{PA} \vdash P$$
\end{thm}
\
\lob{} is at heart a statement about the incompatibility of the interpretation of the box as ``provable''
with the intuitively plausible deduction rule that $\prov \encode{P} \to P$.
(``If we have a proof of $P$, then we can deduce $P$!'')
The Critch paper has an example in Section 1.4 where $P$ is the Riemann hypothesis.
\section{Problem with the paper}
Suppose $\mathcal{M}$ is a model of Peano arithmetic, in which our agent is working.
It is a fact of first-order logic (through the L\"owenheim-Skolem theorem) that there is no first-order way of distinguishing any particular model of PA.
Therefore the model of PA could be non-standard; this is not something a first-order reasoning agent could determine.
If the agent is working with a non-standard model of PA, then all the theorems of the Critch paper may well go through.
However, they become substantially less useful, as follows.
Let us write $M$ for the underlying class (or set) of the model $\mathcal{M}$ of PA. Then the statement $$(\exists \hat{k})[\color{red}(\vdash [\forall k][\color{green}\prov_{f(k)} p(k) \to p(k) \color{red}])\color{black} \Rightarrow \color{blue}(\vdash [\forall k > \hat{k}][p(k)]) \color{black}]$$
when relativised to the model $\mathcal{M}$ becomes
$$(\exists \hat{k} \in M)[\color{red}(\vdash [\forall k \in M][\color{green}\prov^{\mathcal{M}}_{f(k)} p(k) \to p(k) \color{red}])\color{black} \Rightarrow \color{blue}(\vdash [\forall k \in M^{>\hat{k}}][p(k)]) \color{black}]$$
where $\prov^{\mathcal{M}}_{f(k)}$ is now shorthand for ``there is a proof-object $P$ in $M$ such that $P$ encodes a $M$-proof of $p(k)$ which is fewer than $f(k)$ lines long''.
Notice that the quantifiers have been restricted to $M$; in particular, $\hat{k}$ might be a non-standard natural number.
Likewise, the ``there is a proof'' predicate is now ``there is an object which $M$ unpacks into a proof''; but such objects may be non-standard naturals themselves, and unpack into non-standard proofs (which $\mathcal{M}$ still believes are proofs, because it doesn't know the difference between ``standard'' and ``non-standard'').
\subsection{Aside: non-standard proof objects}
What is a non-standard proof object?
Let's imagine we have some specific statements $a_i$ for each natural $i$ such that $a_i \to a_{i+1}$ for each $i$, and such that $a_0$ is an axiom of PA.
I'm using $a_i$ only for shorthand; the reader should imagine I had some specific statements and specific proofs of $a_i \to a_{i+1}$.
Consider the following proof of $a_2$:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $a_0$ (axiom)
\item $a_1$ (by writing out the proof of $a_0 \to a_1$ above this line)
\item $a_2$ (by writing out the proof of $a_1 \to a_2$ above this line)
\end{enumerate}
If we take a simple G\"odel numbering scheme, namely ``take the number to be an ASCII string in base $256$'',
it's easy to see that this proof has a G\"odel number.
After all, we're imagining that I have specific proofs of $a_i \to a_{i+1}$, so I could just write them in.
Then you're reading this document which was originally encoded as ASCII, so the G\"odel numbering scheme must have worked.
Similarly, there is a G\"odel number corresponding to the following:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $a_0$ (axiom)
\item $a_1$ (by writing out the proof of $a_0 \to a_1$ above this line)
\item \dots
\item $a_k$ (by writing out the proof of $a_{k-1} \to a_k$ above this line)
\end{enumerate}
Now, suppose we're working in a non-standard model, and fix non-standard $K$.
Then there is a (probably non-standard) natural $L$ corresponding to the following proof:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $a_0$ (axiom)
\item $a_1$ (by writing out the proof of $a_0 \to a_1$ above this line)
\item \dots
\item $a_K$ (by writing out the proof of $a_{K-1} \to a_K$ above this line)
\end{enumerate}
Now, this is not a ``proof'' in our intuitive sense of the word, because from our perspective it's infinitely long.
However, the model still thinks this is a proof, and that it's coded by the (non-standard) natural $L$.
\subsection{Implication for PBL}
So the model $\mathcal{M}$ believes there is a natural $\hat{k}$ such that \dots
But if that natural is non-standard (and remember that this is not something the model can determine without breaking into second-order logic!)
then PBL doesn't really help us.
It simply tells us that all sufficiently-large non-standard naturals have a certain property; but that doesn't necessarily mean any standard naturals have that property.
And the application to the Prisoners' Dilemma in Critch's paper requires a standard finite $\hat{k}$.
If we, constructing the agent Fairbot, could somehow guarantee that it would be working within the standard model of PA, then all would be well.
However, we can't do that within first-order logic.
It could be the case that when constructing Fairbot, the only sufficiently-large naturals turn out to be non-standard.
When we eventually come to run $\mathrm{Fairbot}_k(\mathrm{Fairbot}_k)$, it could therefore be that it will take nonstandardly-many proof steps to discover the ``(coooperate, cooperate)'' outcome.
In practice, therefore, the agents would not find that outcome: we can only run them for standardly-many steps, and all non-standard naturals look infinite to us.
\section{Acknowledgements}
My thanks are due to Mi\"etek Bak (who persuaded me that there might be a problem with the article)
and to John Aspden (who very capably forced Mi\"etek to clarify his objection until I finally understood it).
As ever, any mistakes in this article are due only to me.
\begin{thebibliography}{9}
\bibitem{critch}
Andrew Critch,
\emph{Parametric Bounded L\"ob's Theorem and Robust Cooperation of Bounded Agents},
\url{http://arxiv.org/abs/1602.04184v4}
\end{thebibliography}
\end{document}